Since
concept always points to itself, it follows that it is always one and the same
regardless of the language being used. For example, I cannot have a concept of
a “table” when in fact I am referring to a chair, and vice versa.
Since this is the case, one
important criterion for a reasoning to be called logical is that concepts are
not confused with one another. In Filipino, we commonly attribute the act of
confusing and misinterpreting concepts as pamimilosopo.
An example would be clear: a mother called her son matigas ang ulo (hard-headed) because he is so stubborn, but the
son reacted that his head is just hard as anybody else, because no head is
soft! The son here confuses the concept of hard-headedness and that of having a
hard head. Ergo, other than being called matigas
ang ulo, the mother adds that her son is also a pilosopo; that is, one
who interprets things obscurely.
To aid us in pointing the error of
reasoning due to confusion of concepts or terms, it is very important to know
what kinds of concepts or terms there are and the laws that govern their
relationship with one another.
KINDS OF
CONCEPTS AND TERMS
A.
Inferior
and Superior Terms
1.
Inferior – is a term known as such because of its
relationship with a superior term by way of specificity. That is, the inferior
is the specification of the superior term. If the superior term is animal, then inferior terms could be bird, fish, deer, etc.
2.
Superior – is a term known as such because of
its relationship with the inferior term by way of generality. That is, the
superior term is the general concept of which the inferior term is a member.
For example, if the inferior term is bird
or cat, then its superior term is
animal. If the inferior term is Filipino, then the superior term is human being.
The general rule in dealing with superior
and inferior terms is that what is true with a superior term may not be true
with an inferior term, but what is true with an inferior term is always true
with a superior term.
This example is invalid:
He
is a teacher.
Therefore
he is a college instructor.
It
does not follow that if one is a teacher (superior term) then one is also a
college instructor (inferior term) since one can be a teacher without being a
college instructor.
But the reverse is valid:
He
is a college instructor.
Therefore
he is a teacher.
This one is incorrect:
If
it is a reptile, then it is a snake.
This one, however, is correct:
If
it is chicken, then it is a bird.
B.
Concrete
and Abstract Concept
1.
Concrete – is a concept that presents to the mind
an individual or a subject possessing a particular attribute
2.
Abstract – is purely an attribute that does not
present to the mind any subject or individual
Examples:
Concrete Abstract
animal “animality”
long “length”
white “whiteness”
human “humanness/humanity”
high “height”
In
making statements using these concepts, one must remember that a concrete term
cannot be predicated with an abstract term, and vice versa.
For
example:
These are incorrect:
The top of Mount
Apo is height.
“The top of Mount Apo” is a concrete term
while “height” is an abstract term.
Humanity is going around in circle.
If not considered as metaphor, this
statement would be incorrect since, strictly speaking, “going around in circle”
(concrete) refers to someone so it cannot be affirmed of “humanity” (abstract
term) which does not refer to anyone.
The following examples commit the same error:
Drinking eight glasses of water a day is goodness.
Beauty harms people.
Love can kill you.
C.
Absolute
and Connotative
1.
Absolute – a concept that presents into the mind
a substance. A substance is something
that is capable of existing on its own as it is.
2.
Connotative – a concept that presents into the
mind something that presupposes a substance.
Examples:
Absolute Connotative
man lazy
sun luminous
wall white
Wall exists as a substance, but white does not. This means that we do
not see white in itself; what we see
is a white wall or a white cloth or a white dress. So white presupposes
an absolute concept (substance) like wall
or cloth or dress in order to exist. In the same way, we do not encounter lazy as it is, what we encounter is a lazy person or a lazy animal. All adjectives are connotative.
One
cannot make use of connotative concepts without presupposing absolute concepts.
For
example, one cannot say:
The
brown jumped over the lazy dog near the river bank, or
The big walked in the dark.
D.
Unconnected
Concepts
Concepts
are unconnected if both of them are inferior
that neither oppose nor include one another. They are called unconnected
because the truth value of one inferior term does not imply, or is not
necessarily connected to, the truth value of the other inferior term. For
example, the statement “Some birds
migrated” does not have anything to do with the statement “Some zebras migrated” because what can
be true to a bird may not be true to
a zebra, both of which are inferior
to the term animal, so they are
unconnected.
Hence,
the general rule is that an inferior term cannot be inferred from another inferior
term.
Here are examples which violate
this rule:
He
is bald.
Therefore,
he is mute.
Filipinos are hospitable, so it follows that Canadians are
hospitable also.
Some
senators are lawyers; therefore, some congressmen are lawyers.
E.
Connected
Concepts
These are concepts so related to one
another that one either exclude or include the other. There are various types
of connected concepts. These are:
1.
Concepts that Include One Another
Examples of these concepts are synonymous
terms, while others are an inferior term and a superior term. There are also
abstract concepts that are so related with one another that one cannot be
thought without including the other. Examples of these concepts could be justice and fairness, freedom and responsibility,
etc. However, the question of whether
these abstract concepts are really related to one another is a philosophical
problem and could not be dealt properly here.
a.
Synonymous terms
One may interchange a term with another
synonymous term without changing the original meaning that one tries to convey.
So, if reasoning proceeds from one term to another synonymous term, it is
valid.
Example:
Those
who labor must receive credit.
The
reward must be in a form of ready money.
Therefore,
those who work must receive cash.
There are three pairs of synonymous terms in
this valid argument: “labor-work”, “credit-reward”, “ready money-cash”.
b.
Superior and Inferior terms
A superior and an inferior term include
one another because both of them can be true in a substance or individual. For
example, something is both a bird and animal, and it would be impossible to be a bird without being an
animal. However, the extent of their inclusion to one another is only limited
in that a superior term and an inferior term may also not be true in a
substance or individual. For example, something can be an animal but not a bird.
Hence, from this observation, we conclude
that what is being affirmed to an inferior term cannot be denied to a superior
term, but not vice versa.
These examples are invalid:
That thing is a plane.
So, it is not a vehicle.
That thing is a bird.
Therefore it is a sparrow.
These
examples, however, are valid:
That
thing is a plane, so it is a vehicle.
That
thing is a bird, so it may be a
sparrow.
2.
Concepts that Exclude One Another
These are concepts whose presence of one
necessarily excludes the other although one cannot be realized without the
other.
These are the types of concepts that
exclude one another:
a.
Relative Concepts
They are called relative concepts because
even if they cannot be simultaneously true in a substance or individual and are
also not opposed to one another, still one cannot be realized without the
other. For example the concepts husband and
wife are relative concepts. Even if no
one can be both a husband and a wife, and even if husband and wife are not
opposed to each other, no one can be called a husband without a concept of wife just as nobody can be called a wife
if there is no concept of husband.
Other examples:
parent – offspring
teacher – student
adviser – advisee
brother – brother/sister
Examples of incorrect statements using
relative concepts:
I
am your father but you are not my son.
Rex
is a follower who does not follow anyone.
“Don
Quixote is a lover without a loved one.”
b.
Contrary Concepts
These are opposing concepts whose
affirmation of one is necessarily a negation of the other, but whose negation
of one does not necessarily mean an affirmation of the other. For example, the
concepts black and white are contrary concepts, so that if
something is black (affirmation), then that something cannot be white
(negation); but, if something is not black (negation), it does not necessarily
mean that that thing is white (affirmation).
Other examples:
good
– evil rational
- irrational
light
– darkness motivated
- unmotivated
boy
– girl intentional
- unintentional
dead
– alive logical
– illogical
These are invalid arguments that use
contrary concepts:
The
font color is not black, so it is white.
If
one is not a boy, then that one is a girl.
That
thing is not alive. Therefore it is dead.
Let
us explain some of them. It does not mean that if one is not a boy then that
one is already a girl since it is
possible that the one being referred to may not have any sex at all. Or, if a
thing is not alive, it does not mean that it is already dead; for example, we
do not call a table or a chair or a stone dead although they are not alive.
c.
Contradictory Concepts
These are opposing concepts whose
affirmation of one necessarily entails negation of the other, and vice versa. For example, black and non-black are contradictory concepts, so if something is black then it is not a non-black, or if something is a non-black then it is not black.
Other examples:
life – lifeless
man – non-man
rational – non-rational
motivated – non-motivated
Sometimes, there is confusion between a
negative contrary concept and a negative contradictory concept.
For example, one confuses between non-rational
and irrational, or non-motivated and unmotivated. Although these concepts appear to be analogous or
synonymous still they are different. That is, it does not mean that if one is non-rational, then that one is irrational, or if something is non-motivated, it does not mean that it
is unmotivated. But the reverse is
not true: if something is dead,
surely it is lifeless, or if
something is white, surely it is non-black.
Examples of invalid arguments because of
confusion between contrary and contradictory concepts:
This life-form is
non-male. So, it is a female.
The
crowd is non-organized, so it is disorganized.
The
feeling is painless; therefore it is pleasurable.
These examples,
however, are valid:
The
feeling is painful; therefore it is not pleasurable.
The
crowd is organized, so it not disorganized.
The
man is blind. Thus, he is sightless.
F.
Univocal,
Equivocal and Analogous Terms
Distinction between univocal, equivocal
and analogous terms is important because it guides us in understanding whether
or not a discourse using any of these kinds of terms deserves merit. Usually,
incorrect reasoning is brought about by confusion on how the term is being used
in a particular discourse.
Let us take this example:
Ilonggo:
Magkadto ta karon. (We will go later)
Cebuano:
Tara na! (Let’s go)
Ilonggo:
Hambal ko karon lang. (I said we’ll
go later)
Cebuano:
Karon gani. Tara na! (You said “now”,
so let’s go)
Karon in this discourse is equivocal. In one sense, it means
“later”; in the other sense, it means “now”. Thus, both the Ilonggo and and the
Cebuano have ignorantly misinterpreted each other.
Consider another example:
Pastor: Let us give our hearts to God.
Child:
Would I not die if I do it?
Pastor: Yes dear child, but to die in God means
life.
Surely, the child and the pastor
do not mean the same thing.
1.
Univocal Terms
A
term is univocal if it is used in a discourse twice or more but in exactly the
same sense.
Examples:
My men are hungry, but your men were filled.
“Pablo” and “Yolanda”
are strong typhoons.
Arroyo and
Aquino were senators.
2.
Equivocal Terms
A term is equivocal if it is used in a
discourse twice or more in a completely different sense.
Examples:
“Yolanda” is a typhoon and a girl.
Alexander
is a man; the picture on the wall is a man.
A
date is a time, but it is also a
romantic appointment.
3.
Analogous Terms
A
term is analogous if it is used in a discourse twice or more in a sense that is
partly the same and partly different.
Examples:
The examination test
is also a test of character.
I am healthy; the
farm is healthy.
The warriors who
died in the battle are warriors of
peace.
To prevent error in reasoning, it is very important that
terms are used univocally. Otherwise, confusion could arise.
Examples:
All
persons are mortals. The picture on
the wall is a person.
Therefore,
the picture in the wall is mortal.
Warriors
kill. The child who defeated cancer is a warrior.
Therefore,
the child kills.
The person in the
first example equivocal, while the warrior
in the second is analogous, both of
which commit the same error.
William Hill Betting Locations | Mapyro
TumugonBurahinFind ventureberg.com/ William Hill sports 바카라 사이트 betting locations 출장마사지 in Maryland, West Virginia, Indiana, https://octcasino.com/ Pennsylvania, South Dakota, West Virginia and more. BetRivers.com.
May I know what reference/book is used? Thank you.
TumugonBurahin